Preface |
|
xvii | |
|
|
|
|
Introduction |
|
xxi | |
|
|
|
|
Select bibliography |
|
lxxiii | |
Translator's Introduction (Abridged) |
|
lxxvii | |
Foreword to First German Edition, Volume I (1900) |
|
1 | (2) |
Foreword to Second German Edition, Volume I (1913) |
|
3 | (6) |
PROLEGOMENA TO PURE LOGIC Volume I of the German Editions |
|
|
Volume I of the German Editions |
|
|
9 | (2) |
|
|
11 | (1) |
|
The controversy regarding the definition of logic and the essential content of its doctrines |
|
|
11 | (1) |
|
Necessity of a renewed discussion of questions of principle |
|
|
12 | (1) |
|
Disputed questions. The path to be entered |
|
|
13 | (2) |
|
Logic as a normative and, in particular, as a practical discipline |
|
|
15 | (13) |
|
The theoretical incompleteness of the separate sciences |
|
|
15 | (1) |
|
The theoretical completion of the separate sciences by metaphysics and theory of science |
|
|
16 | (1) |
|
The possibility and justification of logic as theory of science |
|
|
16 | (3) |
|
Continuation. The three most noteworthy peculiarities of grounded validations |
|
|
19 | (2) |
|
The relation of these peculiarities to the possibility of science and the theory of science |
|
|
21 | (2) |
|
Methodical modes of procedure in the sciences are in part validatory, in part auxiliary devices towards validations |
|
|
23 | (1) |
|
The ideas of theory and science as problems of the theory of science |
|
|
24 | (1) |
|
Logic or theory of science as normative discipline and as technology |
|
|
25 | (1) |
|
Relevant definitions of logic |
|
|
26 | (2) |
|
Theoretical disciplines as the foundation of normative disciplines |
|
|
28 | (12) |
|
The controversy regarding the practical character of logic |
|
|
28 | (5) |
|
The concept of a normative science. The basic standard or principle that gives it unity |
|
|
33 | (4) |
|
Normative disciplines and technologies |
|
|
37 | (1) |
|
Theoretical disciplines as the foundation of normative disciplines |
|
|
38 | (2) |
|
Psychologism, its arguments and its attitude to the usual counter-arguments |
|
|
40 | (6) |
|
The disputed question as to whether the essential theoretical foundations of normative logic lie in psychology |
|
|
40 | (1) |
|
The line of proof of the psychologistic thinkers |
|
|
41 | (1) |
|
The usual arguments of the opposition and the psychologistic rejoinder |
|
|
41 | (3) |
|
A gap in the psychologistic line of proof |
|
|
44 | (2) |
|
Empiricistic consequences of psychologism |
|
|
46 | (10) |
|
Characterizing two empiricistic consequences of the psychologistic standpoint, and their refutation |
|
|
46 | (2) |
|
The laws of thought as supposed laws of nature which operate in isolation as causes of rational thought |
|
|
48 | (3) |
|
A third consequence of psychologism, and its refutation |
|
|
51 | (3) |
|
|
54 | (2) |
|
Psychological interpretations of basic logical principles |
|
|
56 | (14) |
|
The law of contradiction in the psychologistic interpretation of Mill and Spencer |
|
|
56 | (2) |
|
Mill's psychological interpretation of the principle yields no law, but a wholly vague, and scientifically unproven, empirical proposition |
|
|
58 | (3) |
|
Appendix to the last two sections: On certain basic defects of empiricism |
|
|
59 | (2) |
|
Analogous objections against remaining psychological interpretations of our logical principle. Ambiguities as sources of delusion |
|
|
61 | (3) |
|
The supposed two-sidedness of the principle of contradiction, in virtue of which it should be taken both as a natural law of thinking, and as a normal law for its logical regulation |
|
|
64 | (3) |
|
Continuation. Sigwart's doctrine |
|
|
67 | (3) |
|
Syllogistic inferences psychologistically considered. Syllogistic and chemical formulae |
|
|
70 | (5) |
|
Attempts at interpreting syllogistic principles psychologically |
|
|
70 | (2) |
|
Syllogistic and chemical formulae |
|
|
72 | (3) |
|
Psychologism as a sceptical relativism |
|
|
75 | (26) |
|
The ideal conditions for the possibility of a theory as such. The strict concept of scepticism |
|
|
75 | (1) |
|
Scepticism in the metaphysical sense |
|
|
76 | (1) |
|
The concept of relativism and its specific forms |
|
|
77 | (1) |
|
Critique of individual relativism |
|
|
78 | (1) |
|
Critique of specific relativism and, in particular, of anthropologism |
|
|
78 | (4) |
|
General observation. The concept of relativism in an extended sense |
|
|
82 | (1) |
|
Psychologism in all its forms is a relativism |
|
|
82 | (1) |
|
Anthropologism in Sigwart's Logic |
|
|
83 | (7) |
|
Anthropologism in the Logic of B. Erdmann |
|
|
90 | (11) |
|
The psychologistic prejudices |
|
|
101 | (22) |
|
|
101 | (2) |
|
|
103 | (3) |
|
A look back at the opposed arguments of idealism. Their defects and their justified sense |
|
|
106 | (2) |
|
|
108 | (1) |
|
Refutation. Pure mathematics would likewise be made a branch of psychology |
|
|
108 | (1) |
|
The research domain of pure logic is, like that of mathematics, an ideal domain |
|
|
109 | (2) |
|
Confirmatory indications given by the basic notions of logic and the sense of logical laws |
|
|
111 | (2) |
|
|
113 | (2) |
|
Third prejudice. Logic as the theory of evidence |
|
|
115 | (1) |
|
Transformation of logical propositions into equivalent propositions about the ideal conditions for the evidence of judgement. The resultant propositions are not psychological |
|
|
116 | (3) |
|
The decisive points in this dispute |
|
|
119 | (4) |
|
Logic and the principle of the economy of thought |
|
|
123 | (11) |
|
|
123 | (1) |
|
The teleological character of the principle of Mach and Avenarius and the scientific meaning of an `economy of thought' (Denkokonomik) |
|
|
123 | (3) |
|
Closer treatment of the justified ends of an `economy of thought', in the sphere, mainly, of purely deductive methodology. Its relation to a logical technology |
|
|
126 | (3) |
|
The meaninglessness of an economy of thought for pure logic and epistemology, and its relation to psychology |
|
|
129 | (2) |
|
Continuation. The uστεpoν πpoτεpoν involved in any foundation of pure logic on an economy of thought |
|
|
131 | (3) |
|
End of our critical treatments |
|
|
134 | (10) |
|
Queries regarding readily formed misunderstandings of our logical endeavours |
|
|
134 | (1) |
|
Our links with great thinkers of the past and, in the first place, with Kant |
|
|
135 | (1) |
|
Links with Herbart and Lotze |
|
|
136 | (2) |
|
|
138 | (2) |
|
Need for special investigations to provide an epistemological justification and partial realization of the Idea of pure logic |
|
|
140 | (4) |
|
Appendix: References to F. A. Lange and B. Bolzano |
|
|
141 | (3) |
|
|
144 | (16) |
|
The unity of science. The interconnection of things and the interconnection of truths |
|
|
144 | (2) |
|
Continuation. The unity of theory |
|
|
146 | (1) |
|
The essential and extra-essential principles that give science unity. Abstract, concrete and normative sciences |
|
|
147 | (2) |
|
The question as to the ideal conditions of the possibility of science or of theory in general. The question as it relates to actual knowledge |
|
|
149 | (1) |
|
The question as it relates to the content of knowledge |
|
|
150 | (2) |
|
The tasks of pure logic. First: the fixing of the pure categories of meaning, and pure categories of objects and their law-governed combinations |
|
|
152 | (2) |
|
Secondly: the laws and theories which have their grounds in these categories |
|
|
154 | (1) |
|
Thirdly: the theory of the possible forms of theories or the pure theory of manifolds |
|
|
155 | (1) |
|
Elucidation of the Idea of a pure theory of manifolds |
|
|
156 | (2) |
|
Division of labour. The achievement of the mathematicians and that of the philosophers |
|
|
158 | (2) |
|
Broadening of the Idea of pure logic. The pure theory of probability as a pure theory of empirical knowledge |
|
|
160 | |